ABSTRACT
Even though global justice does not require open borders in principle, it imposes significant constraints on how states can exercise their right to exclude in practice. First, rich states have the primary obligation to assist the poor in their home countries, and only a secondary obligation to host those who cannot be assisted where they live. Second, the employment of coercion must be proportional to the objective pursued, such that only in situations of imminent, direct, and serious risk are immigration restrictions justified. Third, whenever it is necessary to limit access, this limitation should be partial and temporary. States must procure alternative transit routes and restore freedom of movement as soon as possible.
Keywords: Global justice; individual autonomy; immigration policy; right to exclude; right to immigrate; open borders; ethics of migration.
RESUMEN
Aunque, en principio, la justicia global no requiera de fronteras abiertas, en la práctica impone restricciones significativas a cómo los Estados pueden ejercer su derecho de exclusión. En primer lugar, los Estados ricos tienen la obligación primaria de asistir a las personas pobres en sus países de origen, y solo una obligación secundaria de acoger a aquellas que no pueden ser asistidas donde viven. En segundo lugar, el empleo de la coacción debe ser proporcional al objetivo perseguido, de manera que solo en situaciones de riesgo inminente, directo y grave están justificadas las restricciones a la inmigración. En tercer lugar, cuando sea necesario limitar el acceso, dicha limitación debe ser parcial y temporal. Los Estados deben procurar vías de tránsito alternativas y restablecer la libertad de circulación lo antes posible.
Palabras clave: Justicia global; autonomía personal; política migratoria; derecho de exclusión; derecho a inmigrar; fronteras abiertas; ética de las migraciones.
International migration takes place against the backdrop of nation-states, in the
sense that it involves leaving one’s country and placing oneself under the jurisdiction
of another. Of course, this is a very simple account of a very complex reality, which
ignores all the obstacles and difficulties along the way. At best, migrants will have
to deal with several bureaucratic procedures and demonstrate that they meet the whole
list of requirements (legal, economic, professional, educational, medical, linguistic,
and so on) to enter another country. All too often, however, migrants, especially
those hailing from the Global South, bump into the closed borders of most states and
are victims of all kinds of abuses. Pushbacks, detentions, internments, deportations,
forced illegality, labor exploitation, discrimination, and criminalization are part
and parcel of the contemporary migration regime. In all these cases, states —of origin,
transit, and above all destination— play a determining role, in the sense that their
migration policies will determine the fate of migrants[1]. In other words, migrants are “at the mercy of the state” (
Attention to this topic by political philosophy is quite recent. The “ethics of migration”,
as it is commonly known, deals with the general principles of justice in migration.
It covers a variety of issues relating to the movement, settlement, and membership
of people in other countries, ranging from the limits on state discretion in the design
of its admission and integration policies to the rights and duties of migrants, including
refugees, family reunification, guest workers, and irregular immigration (
Some authors, by appealing to the ideal of global justice (
Before turning to the discussion, I would like to make two preliminary clarifications
on the scope and methodology of this article. As far as the scope is concerned, the
principles formulated here have migration policies in mind. They do not refer to the
individual action of each person (for example, an employer who decides to hire an
unauthorized migrant), but to the collective decision-making process. Borrowing Miller’s
(
Regarding the methodology, broadly speaking, there are two ways of arguing in the
political philosophy of migration. The first begins with a presumptive right to exclude
and asks what the limits of justice on its exercise are. The second proceeds in reverse,
taking freedom of international movement as the default position, and providing then
for the situations that could justify the suspension of this right. I believe that
the first approach is more fruitful when it comes to discussing the justice of migration
policies, since a human right to immigrate would rule out almost every migration policy
as unjust This contradiction is evident in The Ethics of Immigration by Joseph Carens (
The consequentialist argument for open borders as a requirement of global justice goes something like this:
P1. Global justice requires that everyone in the world has access to the means necessary to lead an autonomous life.
P2. The world in its current state is unjust: millions of people lack access to the means necessary to lead an autonomous life.
P3. Borders (re)produce this injustice, as they prevent access to the means necessary to lead an autonomous life.
P4. A world with open borders would allow these people to access the means necessary to lead an autonomous life.
C. Global justice requires open borders.
This is a remedial argument for open borders in a non-ideal world where many people
lack access to the means necessary to lead an autonomous life (
Even if the premises were true, the conclusion that states are under an obligation
of justice to open their borders is unsound for three reasons. First, global distributive
duties can be discharged in a currency other than the admission of immigrants Other options would be to undertake structural reforms in the international political
and economic institutions, sign fairer trade agreements with developing countries,
establish a global redistributive tax, transfer income directly to the affected countries,
send humanitarian aid, debt cancellation, and capacity building.
This is clearly not the case of refugees, who require admission into another country
( One might counter that remittances represent an abundant source of revenue for many
developing countries, thus compensating for the loss incurred by the departure of
their most skilled citizens (
The deontic argument draws open borders from the application of the principle of moral
equality on a global scale. For cosmopolitan luck egalitarians, the contingencies
of birth should not determine a person’s life chances, and so no one should be disadvantaged
for morally arbitrary facts that escape their control ( Disagreements arise when it comes to interpreting what this moral equality entails.
Some consider that nationality is irrelevant, and that we should treat all people
equally with the exception, perhaps, of loved ones (strong cosmopolitans). For others, some degree of compatriot partiality is permissible and even desirable,
in that it enables a moral division of labor (weak cosmopolitans) (
However, that citizenship is morally arbitrary does not mean that it is irrelevant
from a moral point of view. As Blake (
Finally, it is not only that justice does not require open borders, but it may be
at odds with them. Distributive justice aims at an equitable distribution of the costs
and benefits of social cooperation. Open borders, understood as an unrestricted right
to free movement across the globe, would certainly allow some people to improve their
life prospects by moving to other countries with more opportunities, but they are
by themselves unlikely to produce a fair outcome in the distribution of goods (
In short, global justice does not seem to require open borders because (1) there are
other ways of ensuring the means necessary to lead an autonomous life than opening
borders; (2) justice demands different responses in different contexts, without it
being a deviation from the liberal principles of impartiality and moral equality;
and (3) the imposition of conditions and restrictions on mobility are justified (and
even required) by justice in certain circumstances. Therefore, if we want to defend
open borders, we cannot do so by appealing to global justice. This is not to say that
states have a right to exclude as they see fit. They must still comply with the following
principles of justice in migration policy
The three principles of justice devised here must be understood sequentially and in parallel to the migration process. The principle of assistance acts ex-ante, that is, prior to the departure of the migrant. If migration eventually takes place, the state must respect the principle of self-restraint in the enforcement of border controls. Finally, in those cases where it is necessary to limit freedom of movement, and as long as this limitation persists, the principle of restitution applies.
The principle of assistance imposes the primary obligation upon rich states to fight
against global poverty at source. Only when it is not possible to assist poor people
in their home countries would their resettlement be justified. The admission of immigrants
is therefore a secondary obligation. Rich states have positive duties of justice beyond
their borders, but these can —and should— be discharged in situ without the obligation
to open them. Moreover, there is no duty to admit potential migrants whose needs are
reasonably met where they live I do not intend to defend the right to exclude, but rather to point out that open
borders are not required as a matter of justice. It is still possible that other principles
succeed in grounding a right to immigrate.
1.It does not constitute wrongful discrimination. It would therefore be impermissible to apply any selection criteria on the basis of arbitrary facts such as national origin, ethnicity, beliefs, gender, sexual orientation, or mere linguistic-cultural affinity.
2.The autonomy of migrants is respected. Potential immigrants must be able to develop their life plans, and their needs and legitimate interests must be taken into account.
Regarding the first criterion, states should not make an instrumental use of their
presumptive right to exclude in order to maximize their own interests at any cost
by, say, promoting the immigration of qualified professionals and the great fortunes
to the detriment of the least qualified and worse-off ( A different question is whether this causes deleterious “brain drain”, a problem
that will be dealt with towards the end.
One might worry that these sort of policies are regressive, in the sense that they
benefit the rich at the expense of the poor. However, it depends on how they are implemented.
As I discuss later, the implementation of this proposal would most likely require
concerted action by the international community to ensure that everyone has access
to the basic means of subsistence I am adopting an internationalist conception of global justice, under the assumption
that states have less stringent, but still significant, distributive duties abroad
than at home (
This approach has an advantage over the proposal for open borders. Immigration requires
a minimum of resources and certain skills, something that not everyone possesses.
“The costs of migration, liquidity constraints, limited access to information on conditions
abroad and skill-selective immigration policies prevent people living in poverty from
moving, especially across borders” ( According to Engler et al. ( Others would still prefer to leave, but I will deal with that later. By this I do not mean that people would not continue to have many other reasons to
migrate in a just world. But migration for more trivial or idiosyncratic reasons would
fall outside the realm of justice. This does not mean either that states are allowed
to use whatever means they deem necessary to prevent the arrival of migrants (see
the principle of self-restraint and the principle of restitution in this respect).
In relation to asylum seekers, Wellman (
At this point, I would like to make a clarification. I have said that states are not
obliged to open their borders as a matter of justice, but it does not follow that states are
permitted to do so. For example, some authors reasonably consider that international aid is
preferable to immigration as a means for addressing global poverty, but do not rule
out that immigration be used as a substitute for international aid (e.g.,
One might contend that international aid has long proven to be ineffective, whereas immigration confronts rich countries with the harsh reality, holding them accountable for their own failures. As a matter of fact, people seem to care more about the shipwrecked reaching their shores than the distant poor dying of hunger. I agree that we should not turn away the former, but neither should we abandon the latter. Different policies have different targets, and even though migration policy plays an important role in poverty alleviation, it is in and of itself no effective remedy to global injustice. The ultimate goal should be to improve living standards at home, so that no one is forced to leave to make ends meet.
The second criterion excludes, as we will see in the next sections, the possibility
of deporting someone who has been residing in the host country for a long time ( Someone could object that this too undermines personal autonomy, in that it limits
available options. For the moment, let us note that justice does not require the maximization of life options, but an adequate set of them ( Carens (
The previous principle presumed that states enjoy a broad margin of discretion when
it comes to controlling their borders and regulating admissions. Along with the right
to exclude, I have so far taken the acquiescence of potential immigrants for granted.
But what would happen if they did not abide by the law and persisted in their attempt
to migrate? This question has been explored at length by Hidalgo (
It is very important to provide for the situations that could lead to the suspension
of freedom of international movement, so that the decision is not left to the entire
discretion of the government or the official in charge. To this effect, I propose
three conditions that must be met for immigration restrictions to be justified: (1)
the risk must be imminent, so that there is no less intrusive way to avert it; (2) the risk must be direct, that is, the causal link between freedom of international movement and the unwanted
situation must be straightforward and not the result of multiple independent factors;
(3) the risk must be serious enough to justify the forfeiture of other fundamental rights and freedoms, such as
freedom of movement within the country, freedom of association, or the right of assembly For Yong (
For example, if a massive influx of immigrants jeopardized the welfare system, the government could impose a waiting period on newcomers during which they could not benefit from social welfare programs (first condition unmet). Furthermore, if it is not clear whether freedom of international movement is the main cause of the problem or it stems instead from the perverse incentives of the social benefit system and the situation of poverty in the countries of origin, we might have to tackle these other factors first before restricting immigration (second condition unmet). Finally, if the threat is so serious and the collapse of the system seems imminent, then other equally drastic measures, such as imposing limits on cash withdrawals, increasing the tax burden, or cutting back social benefits, may also be required. But this is rarely the case, which suggests that immigration acts as a scapegoat (third condition unmet). Therefore, none of the three conditions are met, at least for the time being. If we look more closely at the most common reasons for restricting immigration, we will find that they cannot justify a broad right to exclude.
A hypothetical scenario in which these three conditions would converge would be the creation of illegal settlements in the sovereign territory of another country by a foreign power (a kind of neocolonialism). Suppose these settlers were establishing parallel forms of political organization that did not recognize the authority of the central government, such that democratic self-determination and the territorial integrity of the nation were being undermined (first condition met). Suppose, further, that these people came mostly from the same country, a foreign power with expansionist ambitions that was using its population to invade other territories. In this case, the causal link between freedom of international movement and invasion would be more than evident (second condition met). Finally, it seems that the gravity of the situation would require the national government not only to bar the entry of new settlers, but also to expel those who were already residing in these settlements and to dissolve them by force, in other words, to violate other fundamental rights (third condition met). In this scenario, the limitation of freedom of international movement would be justified. In any case, freedom of international movement should be the rule and not the exception.
Self-restraint in the application of coercive measures is a necessary but not sufficient condition for the respect of justice in migration policy. If the risk is so imminent, direct, and serious that the state has no choice but to restrict immigration, such restriction should be temporary and partial: temporary because it should not last longer than strictly necessary, restoring traffic as soon as possible; and partial because alternative routes must be sought after that allow others to travel without incident. In other words, it cannot serve as an excuse to suspend the right to freedom of movement indefinitely and unconditionally.
Returning to the last example, this means that, if the arrival of new settlers from
an occupying force is prohibited, that prohibition should not extend to migrants from
other countries or even to citizens from the invading country who are travelling for
legitimate reasons For example, the prohibition on citizens from some Muslim-majority countries from
traveling to the United States —the so-called Donald Trump’s Muslim ban— was not warranted.
Among other reasons, because it was a total ban, meaning that it was aimed at potential
terrorists and peaceful visitors alike. In addition, judging by its intentionality,
it did not seem to be temporary, but it was introduced on a permanent basis.
In the example of the welfare state, what other routes could be enabled? By routes
I do not mean physical roads or other means of transportation (e.g., by plane or by boat), but solutions that respect as far as possible the spirit of
freedom of movement. If the welfare state was under strain by a massive influx of
immigrants, instead of preventing their access, the state could, in line with the
principle of self-restraint, offer them the following deal: “you can enter the country,
but you must give up social benefits in return, and you will be able to remain as
long as you are self-sufficient” “If the concern is to preserve the integrity of the welfare state, however, the most
that could be justified is restricting membership of the welfare system” (
In short, the government has the complementary obligation to secure alternative routes that allow freedom of movement and to restore traffic as soon as possible, compensating the people who may be affected by its disruption. This is what I have called restitution. If it wants to comply with this principle, the state must ensure the normal flow of people across its borders; and when the only available option is to restrict immigration, it must do so on a temporary and partial basis. In other words, this cannot serve as an excuse to de facto close borders.
At this point, I would like to consider an important objection to this proposal. I started the article by assuming the right of states to control their borders, but I have then affirmed that they have an inexcusable obligation to respect freedom of international movement save for exceptional circumstances. It would seem, then, that I have moved from one strategy to the other, namely, from asserting the presumption of the right to exclude to adopting freedom of international movement as the guiding principle of migration policy.
One possible response to this objection is to note that the two strategies are not
necessarily at odds, and that both come, albeit in a different way, to the same conclusion:
that freedom of international movement must be weighed against the other interests
at stake, such that the degree of openness of a border is a function of the importance
assigned to each of them. As Hidalgo (
Joseph Carens (
My answer is much simpler than that. I acknowledge that this contradiction exists, but I think this is what it takes to respect the autonomy of migrants. As I said before, migration can be a heartbreaking process that involves an abrupt disruption of the life one has built in a place. For this reason, many migrants would prefer not to leave that place if they had an alternative. The principle of assistance responds to this reality by providing poor people with the means necessary to lead an autonomous life, thus offering them an alternative to migration. However, there are other people who would still choose to migrate; people for whom migration is not a desperate way out of their problems, but a way to realize their goals in life. The principle of self-restraint responds to this other reality by respecting the autonomy of migrants to make vital decisions for themselves. Deciding where to live is an essential component of autonomy, and this includes both the decision to stay and the decision to migrate.
Let us now turn to answering some of the questions that may arise from the implementation
of this proposal. What if someone who wishes to migrate for reasons I have previously
called trivial or idiosyncratic has their visa denied in the first place, but nonetheless
persists in their attempt? In such cases, the authorities should take their determination
as a reliable proof of (or as a proxy for) the intensity of their interests and refrain
from using direct physical coercion to prevent their access to and stay in the territory.
This does not preclude the imposition of some bureaucratic and legal barriers. For
example, a state could exclude newcomers from certain public goods and non-essential
services, provided that their basic human rights were not at risk Some might worry that this could lead to racial profiling and other forms of discrimination
against immigrants. According to Mendoza (
Another previous statement was that the authorities could deport immigrants who lack
proper authorization to reside in the country. However, this prerogative diminishes
with the passage of time, as the legitimate interest of the immigrant to remain in
the country increases ( How is it possible to deport someone without exerting physical violence over them?
The state has one of these two options: either to obtain that person’s acquiescence
or to offer them something in return.
I have not dealt with the question of emigration here. Even though, for obvious reasons,
states have less leeway to restrict emigration than immigration, I do not want to
conclude without making some remarks on this question. Immigration cannot be conceived
separate from emigration, and the principles governing the former must be somewhat
consistent with the principles governing the latter According to the general principle of justice in migration put forth by Lea Ypi (
For example, some authors claim that developing countries are justified in preventing
the exodus of their most qualified citizens, either by imposing a period of compulsory
service or a tax on emigration ( Ferracioli (
There is one last question, perhaps the most important one. Can this proposal work in the real world, especially if we bear in mind that states have for their most part been reluctant to take any action in the fight against global injustice? To be honest, I have no satisfactory answer to this question. My guess is that principles of justice in migration are more likely to be implemented at the regional level, where the differences in the standards of living among countries are not large. While this is the best we can hope for at the moment, it can lay the foundations of a future international organization for the governance of migration.
Three conclusions can be drawn from this article: (1) Global justice does not require open borders. (2) Global justice requires respect for the autonomy of migrants. (3) Respect for the autonomy of migrants requires open borders. There is an obvious contradiction here. One of the conclusions must therefore be rejected, but which? It might be that justice only requires respect for the autonomy of citizens, in line with the political conception of justice I have adopted here. Another possibility is that respect for the autonomy of migrants does not require open borders, as the adequate range objection seems to suggest. Lastly, my argument that global justice does not require open borders could be mistaken. I am afraid I cannot offer a definitive answer to this question, but I hope the three principles outlined above can help us find a way out.
I have initially posited that states have broad discretion in the design of their migration policies. However, this does not imply that they can exercise their discretion at will or that they are free of obligations beyond borders. On the one hand, discrimination on arbitrary grounds is prohibited, and the autonomy of migrants must be respected. On the other hand, rich states have positive duties towards the global poor, which should be discharged by assisting them in their countries of origin (principle of assistance); and, where this is not possible, by granting them admission, or alternatively, by paying another country to do so in their place. This principle is mostly useful for forced migrations (whether for reasons of poverty, political persecution, natural disasters, wars, and the like), but it poses serious problems in the case of people who migrate more or less voluntarily. After all, if we ban access to the latter, would we not be undermining their autonomy too?
This is when the next principle comes in, which requires that the degree of coercion be commensurate to the magnitude of the interest at stake. This does not rule out the application of dissuasive measures such as bureaucratic and economic obstacles (indirect coercion), but it does prevent the use of physical force (direct coercion) to restrict freedom of movement when there are less intrusive means, the relationship between the two facts is not proven, and the gravity of the situation is not such that it justifies —and even requires— the limitation of other fundamental rights and freedoms (principle of self-restraint). Only under these conditions can states restrict immigration. It is very important to provide for the specific situations that could lead to the suspension of freedom of movement so that it does not become a catch-all. But this is not enough. The government should enable alternative routes and restore traffic as soon as possible, so that it does not serve as a pretext for suspending freedom of movement indefinitely and across the board (principle of restitution).
These principles have been conceived with liberal democracies in mind, not only because
they are the preferred destination for many migrants, but above all because they reflect
the values that these countries claim to uphold: on the one hand, respect for individual
freedom and personal autonomy, the principle of non-discrimination, social justice,
and the rule of law; on the other, democratic self-determination, national security,
public health, the welfare state, and the legitimate interests of its citizens. These
are the values that, with varying success, I have tried to combine. To ensure a balanced
assessment of all these aspects, it is not a good idea to leave it to the entire discretion
of each state (
In the end, we have moved from a presumptive right to exclude to an actual (albeit
weak) right to immigrate. This move is entailed by a commitment to the autonomy of
migrants, which is itself a requirement of justice. Rich states can and should assist
poor people in their home countries whenever possible, but they cannot hide behind
their right to exclude in order to thwart the life plans of many other people who,
in the exercise of their autonomy, take their fate into their own hands by moving
to another country. Some degree of indirect coercion may be permitted, but with the
passage of time irregular immigrants gain the right to remain, and this is also no
longer valid. The underlying logic behind these principles is that people should be
able to decide where to live and that migrating is a choice, not an obligation. This
begins by ensuring decent living conditions in the countries of origin. Otherwise,
the right to migrate becomes an empty signifier, for people cannot be said to have
the freedom to move if they are forced to move (
[1] |
“While it is true that it is states that have the ultimate power to admit, other
actors can possess a derivative power from the laws that states put in place. By establishing
a system of work visas, for instance, states lend private corporations the power to
nominate foreigners for admission by making job offers” ( |
[2] |
This contradiction is evident in The Ethics of Immigration by Joseph Carens ( |
[3] |
Other options would be to undertake structural reforms in the international political and economic institutions, sign fairer trade agreements with developing countries, establish a global redistributive tax, transfer income directly to the affected countries, send humanitarian aid, debt cancellation, and capacity building. |
[4] |
This is clearly not the case of refugees, who require admission into another country
( |
[5] |
One might counter that remittances represent an abundant source of revenue for many
developing countries, thus compensating for the loss incurred by the departure of
their most skilled citizens ( |
[6] |
Disagreements arise when it comes to interpreting what this moral equality entails.
Some consider that nationality is irrelevant, and that we should treat all people
equally with the exception, perhaps, of loved ones (strong cosmopolitans). For others, some degree of compatriot partiality is permissible and even desirable,
in that it enables a moral division of labor (weak cosmopolitans) ( |
[7] |
The next section draws on Niño Arnaiz ( |
[8] |
I do not intend to defend the right to exclude, but rather to point out that open borders are not required as a matter of justice. It is still possible that other principles succeed in grounding a right to immigrate. |
[9] |
A different question is whether this causes deleterious “brain drain”, a problem that will be dealt with towards the end. |
[10] |
I am adopting an internationalist conception of global justice, under the assumption
that states have less stringent, but still significant, distributive duties abroad
than at home ( |
[11] |
According to Engler et al. ( |
[12] |
Others would still prefer to leave, but I will deal with that later. |
[13] |
By this I do not mean that people would not continue to have many other reasons to migrate in a just world. But migration for more trivial or idiosyncratic reasons would fall outside the realm of justice. This does not mean either that states are allowed to use whatever means they deem necessary to prevent the arrival of migrants (see the principle of self-restraint and the principle of restitution in this respect). |
[14] |
Someone could object that this too undermines personal autonomy, in that it limits
available options. For the moment, let us note that justice does not require the maximization of life options, but an adequate set of them ( |
[15] |
Carens ( |
[16] |
This question has been explored at length by Hidalgo ( |
[17] |
For Yong ( |
[18] |
For example, the prohibition on citizens from some Muslim-majority countries from traveling to the United States —the so-called Donald Trump’s Muslim ban— was not warranted. Among other reasons, because it was a total ban, meaning that it was aimed at potential terrorists and peaceful visitors alike. In addition, judging by its intentionality, it did not seem to be temporary, but it was introduced on a permanent basis. |
[19] |
“If the concern is to preserve the integrity of the welfare state, however, the most
that could be justified is restricting membership of the welfare system” ( |
[20] |
Some might worry that this could lead to racial profiling and other forms of discrimination
against immigrants. According to Mendoza ( |
[21] |
How is it possible to deport someone without exerting physical violence over them? The state has one of these two options: either to obtain that person’s acquiescence or to offer them something in return. |
[22] |
According to the general principle of justice in migration put forth by Lea Ypi ( |
[23] |
Ferracioli ( |
Abizadeh, A. (2008). Democratic Theory and Border Coercion: No Right to Unilaterally Control Your Own Borders. Political Theory, 31 (1), 37-65. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1177/0090591707310090 |
|
Aitchison, G. (2023). Border-Crossing: Immigration Law, Racism and Justified Resistance. Political Studies, 71 (3), 597-615. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1177/00323217211030184 |
|
Al Hashmi, R. (2023). Historical Injustice in Immigration Policy. Political Studies, 71 (4), 1261-1276. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1177/00323217211065557 |
|
Bader, V. (1997). Fairly Open Borders. In V. Bader (ed.). Citizenship and Exclusion (pp. 28-60). London: Macmillan. |
|
Bauböck, R. (2009). Global Justice, Freedom of Movement and Democratic Citizenship. European Journal of Sociology, 50 (1), 1-31. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/S000397560900040X |
|
Blake, M. (2001). Distributive justice, state coercion, and autonomy. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 30 (3), 257-296. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.2001.00257.x |
|
Blake, M. (2002). Discretionary Immigration. Philosophical Topics, 30 (2), 273-289. |
|
Blake, M. (2005). Immigration. In R. G. Frey and C. H. Wellman (eds.). A companion to applied ethics (pp. 224-237). Malden: Blackwell Publishing. |
|
Blake, M. (2008). Immigration and Political Equality. San Diego Law Review, 45 (4), 963-979. |
|
Blake, M. (2013). Immigration, jurisdiction, and exclusion. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 41 (2), 103-130. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/papa.12012 |
|
Blake, M. (2020a). Justice, Migration, and Mercy. New York: Oxford University Press. |
|
Blake, M. (2020b). What is the Border For? Journal of Moral Philosophy, 17 (4), 379-397. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1163/17455243-20192983 |
|
Brock, G. (2009). Global Justice. New York: Oxford University Press. |
|
Brock, G., and Blake, M. (2015). Debating brain drain. New York: Oxford University Press. |
|
Buechel, B. (2023). Beyond the state: the moral nexus between corporations and refugees. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 26 (4), 461-483. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1080/13698230.2020.1764785 |
|
Carens, J. H. (1987). Aliens and Citizens: The Case for Open Borders. The Review of Politics, 49 (2), 251-273. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0034670500033817 |
|
Carens, J. H. (2013). The Ethics of Immigration. New York: Oxford University Press. |
|
Engler, P., Macdonald, M., Piazza, R., and Sher, G. (2020). Migration to Advanced Economies Can Raise Growth. Available at: http://tinyurl.com/4zz23wk8. [Accessed: 18 December 2022] |
|
Ferracioli, L. (2022). Liberal Self-Determination in a World of Migration. New York: Oxford University Press. |
|
Fine, S. (2013). The Ethics of Immigration: Self-Determination and the Right to Exclude. Philosophy Compass, 8 (3), 254-268. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12019 |
|
Fine, S. (2016). Immigration and Discrimination. In S. Fine and L. Ypi (eds.). Migration in Political Theory (pp. 125-150). Oxford: Oxford University Press. |
|
Gibney, M. J. (1999). Liberal Democratic States and Responsibilities to Refugees. American Political Science Review, 93 (1), 169-181. Available at: https://doi.org/10.2307/2585768 |
|
Goodin, R. (1992). If people were money… In B. Barry and R. Goodin (eds.). Free movement: Ethical issues in the transnational migration of people and of money (pp. 6-22). Pennsylvania: Pennsylvania State University Press. |
|
Hidalgo, J. (2014). Freedom, immigration, and adequate options. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 17 (2), 212-234. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1080/13698230.2012.740178 |
|
Hidalgo, J. (2016). The case for the international governance of immigration. International Theory, 8 (1), 140-170. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/S1752971915000226 |
|
Hidalgo, J. (2019). Unjust Borders. New York: Routledge. |
|
Higgins, P. W. (2013). Immigration Justice. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. |
|
Holtug, N. (2020). Global Equality and Open Borders. In D. Sobel, P. Vallentyne, and S. Wall (eds.). Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy, vol. 6 (pp. 118-150). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198852636.003.0005 |
|
Hosein, A. (2014). Immigration: The Argument for Legalization. Social Theory and Practice, 40 (4), 609-630. Available at: https://doi.org/10.5840/soctheorpract201440436 |
|
Hosein, A. (2019). The Ethics of Migration: An Introduction. New York: Routledge. |
|
Huemer, M. (2010). Is there a right to immigrate? Social Theory and Practice, 36 (3), 429-461. Available at: https://doi.org/10.5840/soctheorpract201036323 |
|
Huemer, M. (2019). In Defense of Illegal Immigration. In R. Jones (ed.). Open Borders: In defense of free movement (pp. 34-50). Athens: University of Georgia Press. |
|
Ip, K. K. W. (2020). Selecting Immigrants in an Unjust World. Political Studies, 68 (1), 128-145. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1177/0032321719833885 |
|
Ip, K. K. W. (forthcoming). Immigration enforcement and justifications for causing harm. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 1-24. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1080/13698230.2022.2137751 |
|
James, M. R. (2022). The right to immigrate and responsibility for the past. Journal of Global Ethics, 18 (2), 267-285. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1080/17449626.2022.2086602 |
|
Kukathas, C. (2014). The Case for Open Immigration. In A. I. Cohen and C. H. Wellman (eds.). Contemporary Debates in Applied Ethics (pp. 376-388). Malden: Wiley Blackwell. |
|
Lægaard, S. (2010). What is the Right to Exclude Immigrants? Res Publica, 16, 245-262. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-010-9122-2 |
|
Lister, M. (2010). Immigration, Association, and the Family. Law and Philosophy, 29 (6), 717-745. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10982-010-9083-9 |
|
Lister, M. (2012). Who are Refugees? Law and Philosophy, 32 (5), 645-671. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10982-012-9169-7 |
|
Macedo, S. (2018). The Moral Dilemma of U.S. Immigration Policy Revisited: Open Borders vs. Social Justice? In C. M. Swain (ed.). Debating Immigration (pp. 286-310). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. |
|
Meilander, P. C. (2001). Toward A Theory of Immigration. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. |
|
Mendoza, J. J. (2014). Discrimination and the Presumptive Rights of Immigrants. Critical Philosophy of Race, 2 (1), 68-83. Available at: https://doi.org/10.5325/critphilrace.2.1.0068 |
|
Mendoza, J. J. (2015a). Does cosmopolitan justice ever require restrictions on migration? Public Affairs Quarterly, 29 (2), 175-186. |
|
Mendoza, J. J. (2015b). Enforcement Matters: Reframing the Philosophical Debate over Immigration. Journal of Speculative Philosophy, 29 (1), 73-90. Available at: https://doi.org/10.5325/jspecphil.29.1.0073 |
|
Miller, D. (2014). Immigration: The Case for Limits. In A. I. Cohen and C. H. Wellman (eds.). Contemporary Debates in Applied Ethics (pp. 363-375). Malden: Wiley Blackwell. |
|
Miller, D. (2016a). Is There a Human Right to Immigrate? In S. Fine and L. Ypi (eds.). Migration in Political Theory (pp. 11-31). Oxford: Oxford University Press. |
|
Miller, D. (2016b). Strangers in our midst. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. |
|
Miller, D. (2023). Authority and Immigration. Political Studies, 71 (3), 835-850. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1177/00323217211046423 |
|
Nagel, T. (2005). The Problem of Global Justice. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 33 (2), 113-147. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.2005.00027.x |
|
Niño Arnaiz, B. (2023). Tres principios de justicia en la política migratoria. Arbor, 199 (809), a176. https://doi.org/10.3989/arbor.2023.809005 |
|
Oberman, K. (2011). Immigration, Global Poverty and the Right to Stay. Political Studies, 29 (2), 253-268. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.2011.00889.x |
|
Oberman, K. (2015). Poverty and Immigration Policy. American Political Science Review, 109 (2), 239-251. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0003055415000106 |
|
Oberman, K. (2016). Immigration as a Human Right. In S. Fine and L. Ypi (eds.). Migration in Political Theory (pp. 32-56). Oxford: Oxford University Press. |
|
Pevnick, R. (2011). Immigration and the Constraints of Justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. |
|
Pogge, T. (1997). Migration and Poverty. In V. Bader (ed.). Citizenship and Exclusion (pp. 12-27). London: Macmillan. |
|
Sager, A. (2017). Immigration Enforcement and Domination: An Indirect Argument for Much More Open Borders. Political Research Quarterly, 70 (1), 42-54. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1177/1065912916680036 |
|
Sandelind, C. (2015). Territorial rights and open borders. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 18 (5), 487-507. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1080/13698230.2013.864796 |
|
Sandelind, C. (2021). Costs of refugee admission and the ethics of extraterritorial protection. European Journal of Political Theory, 20 (1), 116-137. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1177/1474885117738118 |
|
Seglow, J. (2005). The Ethics of Immigration. Political Studies Review, 3 (3), 317-334. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1478-9299.2005.00026.x |
|
Seglow, J. (2006). Immigration justice and borders: Towards a global agreement. Contemporary Politics, 12 (3-4), 233-246. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1080/13569770601086154 |
|
Shachar, A. (2009). The Birthright Lottery. London: Harvard University Press. |
|
Shachar, A. (2020). The Shifting Border. Manchester: Manchester University Press. |
|
Sharp, D. (2022). Relational Equality and Immigration. Ethics, 132 (3), 644-679. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1086/718076 |
|
Song, S. (2016). The Significance of Territorial Presence and the Rights of Immigrants. In S. Fine and L. Ypi (eds.). Migration in Political Theory (pp. 225-248). Oxford: Oxford University Press. |
|
Song, S. (2017). Why Does the State Have the Right to Control Immigration? In J. Knight (ed.). NOMOS LVII: Migration, Emigration, and Immigration (pp. 3-50). New York: New York University Press. |
|
Song, S. (2019). Immigration and Democracy. New York: Oxford University Press. |
|
Stilz, A. (2016). Is there an unqualified right to leave? In S. Fine and L. Ypi (eds.). Migration in Political Theory (pp. 57-79). Oxford: Oxford University Press. |
|
Stilz, A. (2022). Economic Migration: On What Terms? Perspectives on Politics, 20 (3), 983-998. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/S1537592721002206 |
|
UN DESA (2020). World Social Report 2020: Inequality in a rapidly changing world. Available at: http://tinyurl.com/yh8ajyyb. [Accessed: 18 December 2022] |
|
Walzer, M. (1983). Spheres of Justice. New York: Basic Books. |
|
Wellman, C. H. (2008). Immigration and Freedom of Association. Ethics, 119 (1), 109-141. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1086/592311 |
|
Wellman, C. H. (2016). Freedom of Movement and the Rights to Enter and Exit. In S. Fine and L. Ypi (eds.). Migration in Political Theory (pp. 80-101). Oxford: Oxford University Press. |
|
Wellman, C. H., and Cole, P. (2011). Debating the ethics of immigration. New York: Oxford. |
|
Wilcox, S. (2007). Immigrant Admissions and Global Relations of Harm. Journal of Social Philosophy, 38 (2), 274-291. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9833.2007.00379.x |
|
Wilcox, S. (2014). Do duties to outsiders entail open borders? A reply to Wellman. Philosophical Studies, 169, 123-132. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-9902-y |
|
Yong, C. (2017). Immigration Rights and the Justification of Immigration Restrictions. Journal of Social Philosophy, 48 (4), 461-480. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/josp.12212 |
|
Yong, C. (2018). Justifying Resistance to Immigration Law: The Case of Mere Noncompliance. Canadian Journal of Law & Jurisprudence, 31 (2), 459-481. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/cjlj.2018.20 |
|
Ypi, L. (2008). Justice in Migration: A Closed Borders Utopia? Journal of Political Philosophy, 16 (4), 391-418. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9760.2008.00326.x |